American Renaissance for the Twenty-first Century | Article
Thoughts on Musical Characterization and Plot:
The Symbolic and Emotional Power of Dramatic Music
by Roger E. Bissel
It was Aristotle who first
spoke of the similarity between our experiences of music and
drama. In the Politics, he referred to music as the most
"imitative" of the arts: ". . . music produces by its sounds
the same effects that nature produces by human character in
action. A good poem or a good song arouses in us the same
feelings and emotions as do the actions of a man." More
recently, German physiologist and physicist Hermann
Helmholtz held that music can imitate and express not only
overt physical motions but also "the mental conditions which
naturally evoke similar emotions, whether of the body or
voice . . ."
Unfortunately, the insights of Aristotle and Helmholtz have
not had a great influence upon modern music aestheticians,
who view music as wholly emotive with no base in reason, or
wholly mathematical and formalistic, devoid of emotion. But
in fact music can be grounded in realist and
representational aesthetics. Dramatic music (meaning music
with a plot structure, music that builds to a climax and
seeks resolution) has emotional power specifically because
its musical characterization and plot symbolize a world in
which human life is purposeful. Such music arouses emotions
by setting up an aural microcosm in which one can view and
respond to an image of human experience and goal-directed
action.
In general, symbols are concretes that stand for and thus
bring to mind some idea. Linguistic symbols (language), can
be used to symbolize any and all ideas. Music and the other
arts, by contrast, are comprised of aesthetic symbols, which
are radically different from linguistic symbols. They do not
rely upon conventionally accepted and memorized meanings,
but instead present images or feelings that are
automatically seen as embodying a meaning. As such, the
greatest usefulness of aesthetic symbols lies in their
ability to stand for certain deep abstractions about reality
and human existence--and thus to symbolize a world or
microcosm that exemplifies that abstraction. Music can also
present a microcosmic view of human experience and
goal-directed action. It does so, in striking parallel to
great literature, by employing musical characterization and
musical plot.
In order to effectively utilize musical characterization and
plot, the composer must organize the musical "events" so
that the listener can perceptually integrate them. An
arrangement of tones of varying intervals, pitches,
durations, articulations, etc., becomes a melody. A
multilayered progression of melody and harmonic-rhythmic
accompaniment becomes a musical form. Musical
characterization, then, is the composer's means for inducing
listeners to experience a melody as if it were a single
dynamic musical entity behaving in a certain way and/or
having things happen to it--and musical plot is the
composer's means for inducing listeners to experience a
musical form as if it were a single dynamic musical process,
an intricate system of means and ends (or causes and
effects) aiming at a certain musical goal(s).
Both of these elements are present in dramatic music, and a
listener is able to fully benefit from its symbolic and
emotional power by engaging with these elements. This is
done by adopting what John Hospers calls "the aesthetic
attitude"--detaching from one's own real-world concerns and
absorbing oneself in the "world" of the musical piece. In
this manner, listeners are then able to "identify with" the
musical entity (melody), its physical behavior, and its
goal-directed action--much as they do when reading about or
viewing a dramatic character. They can then evaluate the
things that happen to the melody and in the musical form
(and, vicariously, to themselves and in their lives) as good
or bad, and respond accordingly--again, as in their
experience of literary or theatrical drama.
Presuming, then, that dramatic music is often experienced as
presenting analogies to human experience and
goal-directedness, how is it able to do this so effectively?
The explanation lies partly in the fact that underlying
these purposive analogies is a more basic physical one: our
perception of musical tones as having a location, and being
in motion.
It is sometimes thought that our awareness of musical sounds
is a process not of perception but of sensation. Helmholtz
himself speaks of "sensation" and so gives the impression
that music is a matter of raw sense--following philosopher
William James, a chaotic, undifferentiated, "bloomin',
buzzin' confusion." This could not be more unlike our
experience of music. Although sound waves are physically
mixed together, we are capable of perceptually singling out
any given individual sound. By suppressing the physiological
effect on our hearing apparatus of other competing sound
waves, we experience it as a sound, as a chirp, tweet,
rattle, buzz, honk, voice, tone, or whatever. Since we
definitely hear musical sounds as discrete, differentiated
units of awareness, musical awareness is clearly a form of
perception, not sensation. Our perception of tones, (or
sounds of definite pitch), is particularly important to
music. While we have little or no auditory awareness of the
actual spatial location of a sound wave or the entity
emitting it, tones can present a striking metaphor or
analogy to location and motion. This analogy is experienced
in relation to the tonal attribute of pitch.
Pitch is not experienced as a quality similar to color, even
though both are correlated with frequency of energy waves.
Instead, we experience tonal pitch as having a definite
spatial location, one experienced as being in a vertical
dimension. Tones of greater frequency are heard as "higher"
in pitch, and tones of lesser frequency as "lower." We
further experience change in pitch as being in a forward
direction, analogous to actual spatial motion. But what is
moving? An entity? Is a single tone an entity? If so, then
why is a melodic succession of tones not perceived as a
succession of discrete entities, but instead as one entity
extended in time and moving through musical space? Or, if a
single tone is not an entity, how does its combination with
other tones allow it to be perceived as one?
The perception of motion in music is due to an aural version
of the phi-phenomenon. This is the process whereby the brain
integrates a series of events (sufficiently similar and
close enough in space and time) into a single unit. This is
why we experience a semblance of motion in television and
movies, which, as we know, are made up of many single
picture frames projected in quick succession. Thus, because
musical awareness is not the sensation of an indistinct
flurry of activity but rather the perception of an
integrated series of similar distinct tones (and because
changes in those tones are interpreted as motion), we in
effect perceive music as entities in motion.
Yet, the mystery about music is not how it symbolizes
motion, but how it symbolizes emotion. Motion as such does
not reliably convey emotion in literature--we don't weep upon
reading that someone opened a door--so how can it do any
differently in music? It doesn't. Even though music often
symbolizes motion of perceivable entities, there is no
strictly musical reason why perceiving a musical image of
entities in motion should have value significance. The
answer lies in how music builds on the image of motion and
location to achieve a further image of human experience and
goal-directed action.
In theatrical drama, we are presented with suggestions of
the emotional states, intentions, and expectations of the
characters. These emotions are not usually suggested by
verbal description but instead by inference from gestures,
posture, and facial expressions. We associate these with
certain inner states that we know from real-life experience.
Then, seeing them on the stage, we infer the presence of
those emotions, intentions, and expectations in the dramatic
characters. The actress stands bolt upright, turns in
surprise, goes forward, hesitates, then resumes her motion
with a rush. "Yes," we might say, seeing her actions and
expressions, "that's a convincing portrayal. That actress
looks surprised, upset, purposeful." Of course, depending on
her method of acting, she may or may not experience such
emotions in fact. Yet through the medium of body language,
she can establish the character's values, goals, and inner
states without even a single word of dialogue being uttered.
By analogy, the same can be true in music. This mode of
suggesting emotions or goals or mental states in music rests
on the analogy to motion and position in space, conveyed
mainly by the elements of melody and rhythm. The sense of
motion and position evoked by a given combination of tones
bears striking analogy to gestures and postures accompanying
such states in real life. A master of this gestural aspect
of music was Franz Liszt, particularly in his Hungarian
Rhapsodies (put to effective use in numerous mid-twentieth
century cartoon sound tracks). This factor is a basic reason
why music can so naturally be combined with dance; abrupt
changes in the range of pitch spanned by the harmony, sudden
melodic changes in pitch, etc., all have direct counterparts
in choreography--and in human emotions. Tchaikovsky's ballets
The Nutcracker Suite and Swan Lake come to mind here (the
former playing a prominent role in the classic Disney
animated feature, Fantasia). As somewhat of an historical
irony, Liszt was a prominent proponent of the practice of
prefixing passages of explanatory material (programmes) to
his symphonic poems. There was a 300-year tradition of such
programme music preceding him--which continues today in
concert notes and liner notes for recorded music--but Liszt
could well have dispensed with the literary appendages and
allowed the emotional, plotful directness of his music to
speak for itself.
Concrete-level emotions are suggested in music by a musical
impression of the physical accompaniments of the emotions.
This works well because emotions are motivational, they have
implications for physical motion such that, in retrospect,
motion of a certain character is taken to imply a certain
kind of emotion. (As another example of this point, consider
the music for the dance scenes in Bernstein's West Side
Story.) Abstract-level progressions of emotions are
suggested in music by a series of musical events that
generate, develop, and resolve (or thwart) the listener's
expectations. This works because emotions are a response to
value-judgments, and value-judgments are the basis of
purposeful action, as symbolized by plot--in music, as in
literature. Much of the continuing popularity of
Shostakovich's Fifth Symphony, for example, probably lies in
the power of its Finale movement, which works in just this
way. The manner by which certain melodic fragments are
developed in the first three movements should not be
overlooked, however, for they are the seeds of the
full-blown theme of the Finale. Thus there are two levels:
first, each of the dramatic arts can function in its own
peculiar way (verbal reference, acting out, or aural
analogy), using very compact sequences to convey an instant
impression of some physical concomitant; each has its own
"language" on a concrete, short-range level. Second, the
more abstract level involves higher forms of perceptual
integration--the progression to the climax and the subsequent
resolution of the action, using the "words" or musical
events to form a story. Each of the vignettes or elements or
"words" in this "language" takes on additional color and
depth because of where it is placed in the overall sequence.
Neither dramatic music, nor literature, nor drama is merely
a series of events in temporal succession, like beads on a
string, with no significance beyond the range-of-the-moment.
In a goal-directed progression, events on one level are
related as means to events on a broader level, which are the
ends. In turn, these ends serve as the means to events on
the next higher level, and so on up the hierarchy of events
to the ultimate goal of that given progression. The mental
process one uses to grasp such a multi-level artistic
progression is very similar to that involved in experiencing
real life events. This process--technically known as
identification--is the means by which one temporarily
suspends one's own personal context and puts oneself in the
place of other persons--whether in real life, characters in
drama or through harmonic developments in music.
Identification is also involved in recognizing the
individual elements of the piece--again, the separate "words"
of the musical "language"--but it is called upon much more
fully in grasping the musical plot. These two responses then
work together to heighten the impact of the music. A dashing
and defiant melody can strengthen the effect of a victorious
musical progression, significantly more so than a dignified
and stately melody. The fact that there are distinct layers
of meaning--that a passage joyful in itself can be expanded
to an even wider context to suggest irony, or counterpoint a
deeper triumph, or portend doom--means the potential for
conflict, which is vital.
Melody, harmony, and rhythm shape the musical progression
and every segment of it. Conflict typically is found in all
three. One cannot construct a very interesting plot by
arranging for an undistinguished, humdrum, non-dissonant
march straight to the musical goal; this would convey the
impression that there are no obstacles, no excitement or
challenges in life. Instead, the musical plot dramatizes
goal-directedness by employing conflict--whether in the
implied goals of a single melodic idea, or between two or
more melodic ideas, or within corresponding harmonies, or in
other ways. The analogy of plotful music to literature and
drama is profound and vivid.
The seminal figure in music history for this aspect of the
composer's craft was Beethoven. The first movement of his
Fifth Symphony (referred to during World War II as the
"Victory" Symphony, for the similarity of its opening motif--da-da-da-daaaah--to
the Morse Code symbol for the letter "V") is a perfect
example. The way in which he delays and then unexpectedly
resolves the musical progression in the first movement
presents the listener with a suspenseful, intense conflict
of the first order. Beethoven was a master at using smaller
structural units as building blocks, joining them together
into a logical succession by the common rhythmic and melodic
features that they shared, and then using them to develop
toward points of climax and resolution in his musical works.
The kind of structure Beethoven provides the attentive
listener is the basis of our perception of goal-directedness
in music. Because of how the system of musical relationships
develops, one expects certain events to follow others, one's
expectations are fulfilled or denied, and one responds
accordingly. The music strains to rise, falls, rises again;
it surges forward, pauses, clashes, swoops and soars.
The core of goal-directedness in music, then, is our
perception of entities as being in motion and our
expectation that these entities will find an appropriate
point at which to resolve their motion. The resolution of a
chord progression and the resolution of a literary plot are
fundamentally similar--enough so that it is altogether
reasonable to extend the concept of plot to apply to
progressions of musical events. This does not imply that all
worthwhile music must have goal-directed action, but it does
suggest that one's response to dramatic music is not just a
knee-jerk and does have a rational basis in form. Such music
does not mean just anything the listener or composer wants
it to mean; the meaning arises from the events.
On this matter, as so many others, Aristotle was right:
dramatic music and dramatic literature are profoundly
similar.
Roger Bissell is a professional musician and writer on psychology and philosophy, whose work has appeared in Reason, Objectivity, and numerous other magazines. This essay is adapted from a longer manuscript on the nature of aesthetics, originally commissioned in 1971, and appears with the permission of the Equitarian Associates (Milo Schield, Douglas Rasmussen, and Joel Myklebust), without whose encouragement and generous financial assistance it would not have been written.